Better-quasi-ordering

In order theory a better-quasi-ordering or bqo is a quasi-ordering that does not admit a certain type of bad array. Every better-quasi-ordering is a well-quasi-ordering.

Motivation

Though well-quasi-ordering is an appealing notion, many important infinitary operations do not preserve well-quasi-orderedness. An example due to Richard Rado illustrates this.[1] In a 1965 paper Crispin Nash-Williams formulated the stronger notion of better-quasi-ordering in order to prove that the class of trees of height ω is well-quasi-ordered under the topological minor relation.[2] Since then, many quasi-orderings have been proven to be well-quasi-orderings by proving them to be better-quasi-orderings. For instance, Richard Laver established Laver's theorem (previously a conjecture of Roland Fraïssé) by proving that the class of scattered linear order types is better-quasi-ordered.[3] More recently, Carlos Martinez-Ranero has proven that, under the proper forcing axiom, the class of Aronszajn lines is better-quasi-ordered under the embeddability relation.[4]

Definition

It is common in better-quasi-ordering theory to write x {\displaystyle {_{*}}x} for the sequence x {\displaystyle x} with the first term omitted. Write [ ω ] < ω {\displaystyle [\omega ]^{<\omega }} for the set of finite, strictly increasing sequences with terms in ω {\displaystyle \omega } , and define a relation {\displaystyle \triangleleft } on [ ω ] < ω {\displaystyle [\omega ]^{<\omega }} as follows: s t {\displaystyle s\triangleleft t} if there is u [ ω ] < ω {\displaystyle u\in [\omega ]^{<\omega }} such that s {\displaystyle s} is a strict initial segment of u {\displaystyle u} and t = u {\displaystyle t={}_{*}u} . The relation {\displaystyle \triangleleft } is not transitive.

A block B {\displaystyle B} is an infinite subset of [ ω ] < ω {\displaystyle [\omega ]^{<\omega }} that contains an initial segment[clarification needed] of every infinite subset of B {\displaystyle \bigcup B} . For a quasi-order Q {\displaystyle Q} , a Q {\displaystyle Q} -pattern is a function from some block B {\displaystyle B} into Q {\displaystyle Q} . A Q {\displaystyle Q} -pattern f : B Q {\displaystyle f\colon B\to Q} is said to be bad if f ( s ) Q f ( t ) {\displaystyle f(s)\not \leq _{Q}f(t)} [clarification needed] for every pair s , t B {\displaystyle s,t\in B} such that s t {\displaystyle s\triangleleft t} ; otherwise f {\displaystyle f} is good. A quasi-ordering Q {\displaystyle Q} is called a better-quasi-ordering if there is no bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -pattern.

In order to make this definition easier to work with, Nash-Williams defines a barrier to be a block whose elements are pairwise incomparable under the inclusion relation {\displaystyle \subset } . A Q {\displaystyle Q} -array is a Q {\displaystyle Q} -pattern whose domain is a barrier. By observing that every block contains a barrier, one sees that Q {\displaystyle Q} is a better-quasi-ordering if and only if there is no bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array.

Simpson's alternative definition

Simpson introduced an alternative definition of better-quasi-ordering in terms of Borel functions [ ω ] ω Q {\displaystyle [\omega ]^{\omega }\to Q} , where [ ω ] ω {\displaystyle [\omega ]^{\omega }} , the set of infinite subsets of ω {\displaystyle \omega } , is given the usual product topology.[5]

Let Q {\displaystyle Q} be a quasi-ordering and endow Q {\displaystyle Q} with the discrete topology. A Q {\displaystyle Q} -array is a Borel function [ A ] ω Q {\displaystyle [A]^{\omega }\to Q} for some infinite subset A {\displaystyle A} of ω {\displaystyle \omega } . A Q {\displaystyle Q} -array f {\displaystyle f} is bad if f ( X ) Q f ( X ) {\displaystyle f(X)\not \leq _{Q}f({_{*}}X)} for every X [ A ] ω {\displaystyle X\in [A]^{\omega }} ; f {\displaystyle f} is good otherwise. The quasi-ordering Q {\displaystyle Q} is a better-quasi-ordering if there is no bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array in this sense.

Major theorems

Many major results in better-quasi-ordering theory are consequences of the Minimal Bad Array Lemma, which appears in Simpson's paper[5] as follows. See also Laver's paper,[6] where the Minimal Bad Array Lemma was first stated as a result. The technique was present in Nash-Williams' original 1965 paper.

Suppose ( Q , Q ) {\displaystyle (Q,\leq _{Q})} is a quasi-order.[clarification needed] A partial ranking {\displaystyle \leq '} of Q {\displaystyle Q} is a well-founded partial ordering of Q {\displaystyle Q} such that q r q Q r {\displaystyle q\leq 'r\to q\leq _{Q}r} . For bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -arrays (in the sense of Simpson) f : [ A ] ω Q {\displaystyle f\colon [A]^{\omega }\to Q} and g : [ B ] ω Q {\displaystyle g\colon [B]^{\omega }\to Q} , define:

g f  if  B A  and  g ( X ) f ( X )  for every  X [ B ] ω {\displaystyle g\leq ^{*}f{\text{ if }}B\subseteq A{\text{ and }}g(X)\leq 'f(X){\text{ for every }}X\in [B]^{\omega }}
g < f  if  B A  and  g ( X ) < f ( X )  for every  X [ B ] ω {\displaystyle g<^{*}f{\text{ if }}B\subseteq A{\text{ and }}g(X)<'f(X){\text{ for every }}X\in [B]^{\omega }}

We say a bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array g {\displaystyle g} is minimal bad (with respect to the partial ranking {\displaystyle \leq '} ) if there is no bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array f {\displaystyle f} such that f < g {\displaystyle f<^{*}g} . The definitions of {\displaystyle \leq ^{*}} and < {\displaystyle <'} depend on a partial ranking {\displaystyle \leq '} of Q {\displaystyle Q} . The relation < {\displaystyle <^{*}} is not the strict part of the relation {\displaystyle \leq ^{*}} .

Theorem (Minimal Bad Array Lemma). Let Q {\displaystyle Q} be a quasi-order equipped with a partial ranking and suppose f {\displaystyle f} is a bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array. Then there is a minimal bad Q {\displaystyle Q} -array g {\displaystyle g} such that g f {\displaystyle g\leq ^{*}f} .

See also

References

  1. ^ Rado, Richard (1954). "Partial well-ordering of sets of vectors". Mathematika. 1 (2): 89–95. doi:10.1112/S0025579300000565. MR 0066441.
  2. ^ Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (1965). "On well-quasi-ordering infinite trees". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 61 (3): 697–720. Bibcode:1965PCPS...61..697N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100039062. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0175814. S2CID 227358387.
  3. ^ Laver, Richard (1971). "On Fraïssé's Order Type Conjecture". The Annals of Mathematics. 93 (1): 89–111. doi:10.2307/1970754. JSTOR 1970754.
  4. ^ Martinez-Ranero, Carlos (2011). "Well-quasi-ordering Aronszajn lines". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 213 (3): 197–211. doi:10.4064/fm213-3-1. ISSN 0016-2736. MR 2822417.
  5. ^ a b Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "BQO Theory and Fraïssé's Conjecture". In Mansfield, Richard; Weitkamp, Galen (eds.). Recursive Aspects of Descriptive Set Theory. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press. pp. 124–38. ISBN 978-0-19-503602-2. MR 0786122.
  6. ^ Laver, Richard (1978). "Better-quasi-orderings and a class of trees". In Rota, Gian-Carlo (ed.). Studies in foundations and combinatorics. Academic Press. pp. 31–48. ISBN 978-0-12-599101-8. MR 0520553.
  • v
  • t
  • e
Key conceptsResultsProperties & Types (list)ConstructionsTopology & OrdersRelated