Factorization system

In mathematics, it can be shown that every function can be written as the composite of a surjective function followed by an injective function. Factorization systems are a generalization of this situation in category theory.

Definition

A factorization system (E, M) for a category C consists of two classes of morphisms E and M of C such that:

  1. E and M both contain all isomorphisms of C and are closed under composition.
  2. Every morphism f of C can be factored as f = m e {\displaystyle f=m\circ e} for some morphisms e E {\displaystyle e\in E} and m M {\displaystyle m\in M} .
  3. The factorization is functorial: if u {\displaystyle u} and v {\displaystyle v} are two morphisms such that v m e = m e u {\displaystyle vme=m'e'u} for some morphisms e , e E {\displaystyle e,e'\in E} and m , m M {\displaystyle m,m'\in M} , then there exists a unique morphism w {\displaystyle w} making the following diagram commute:


Remark: ( u , v ) {\displaystyle (u,v)} is a morphism from m e {\displaystyle me} to m e {\displaystyle m'e'} in the arrow category.

Orthogonality

Two morphisms e {\displaystyle e} and m {\displaystyle m} are said to be orthogonal, denoted e m {\displaystyle e\downarrow m} , if for every pair of morphisms u {\displaystyle u} and v {\displaystyle v} such that v e = m u {\displaystyle ve=mu} there is a unique morphism w {\displaystyle w} such that the diagram

commutes. This notion can be extended to define the orthogonals of sets of morphisms by

H = { e | h H , e h } {\displaystyle H^{\uparrow }=\{e\quad |\quad \forall h\in H,e\downarrow h\}} and H = { m | h H , h m } . {\displaystyle H^{\downarrow }=\{m\quad |\quad \forall h\in H,h\downarrow m\}.}

Since in a factorization system E M {\displaystyle E\cap M} contains all the isomorphisms, the condition (3) of the definition is equivalent to

(3') E M {\displaystyle E\subseteq M^{\uparrow }} and M E . {\displaystyle M\subseteq E^{\downarrow }.}


Proof: In the previous diagram (3), take m := i d ,   e := i d {\displaystyle m:=id,\ e':=id} (identity on the appropriate object) and m := m {\displaystyle m':=m} .

Equivalent definition

The pair ( E , M ) {\displaystyle (E,M)} of classes of morphisms of C is a factorization system if and only if it satisfies the following conditions:

  1. Every morphism f of C can be factored as f = m e {\displaystyle f=m\circ e} with e E {\displaystyle e\in E} and m M . {\displaystyle m\in M.}
  2. E = M {\displaystyle E=M^{\uparrow }} and M = E . {\displaystyle M=E^{\downarrow }.}

Weak factorization systems

Suppose e and m are two morphisms in a category C. Then e has the left lifting property with respect to m (respectively m has the right lifting property with respect to e) when for every pair of morphisms u and v such that ve = mu there is a morphism w such that the following diagram commutes. The difference with orthogonality is that w is not necessarily unique.

A weak factorization system (E, M) for a category C consists of two classes of morphisms E and M of C such that:[1]

  1. The class E is exactly the class of morphisms having the left lifting property with respect to each morphism in M.
  2. The class M is exactly the class of morphisms having the right lifting property with respect to each morphism in E.
  3. Every morphism f of C can be factored as f = m e {\displaystyle f=m\circ e} for some morphisms e E {\displaystyle e\in E} and m M {\displaystyle m\in M} .

This notion leads to a succinct definition of model categories: a model category is a pair consisting of a category C and classes of (so-called) weak equivalences W, fibrations F and cofibrations C so that

  • C has all limits and colimits,
  • ( C W , F ) {\displaystyle (C\cap W,F)} is a weak factorization system,
  • ( C , F W ) {\displaystyle (C,F\cap W)} is a weak factorization system, and
  • W {\displaystyle W} satisfies the two-out-of-three property: if f {\displaystyle f} and g {\displaystyle g} are composable morphisms and two of f , g , g f {\displaystyle f,g,g\circ f} are in W {\displaystyle W} , then so is the third.[2]

A model category is a complete and cocomplete category equipped with a model structure. A map is called a trivial fibration if it belongs to F W , {\displaystyle F\cap W,} and it is called a trivial cofibration if it belongs to C W . {\displaystyle C\cap W.} An object X {\displaystyle X} is called fibrant if the morphism X 1 {\displaystyle X\rightarrow 1} to the terminal object is a fibration, and it is called cofibrant if the morphism 0 X {\displaystyle 0\rightarrow X} from the initial object is a cofibration.[3]

References

  1. ^ Riehl (2014, §11.2)
  2. ^ Riehl (2014, §11.3)
  3. ^ Valery Isaev - On fibrant objects in model categories.
  • Peter Freyd, Max Kelly (1972). "Categories of Continuous Functors I". Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra. 2.
  • Riehl, Emily (2014), Categorical homotopy theory, Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/CBO9781107261457, ISBN 978-1-107-04845-4, MR 3221774

External links

  • Riehl, Emily (2008), Factorization Systems (PDF)